Find link

language:

jump to random article

Find link is a tool written by Edward Betts.

Longer titles found: Material implication (rule of inference) (view), Paradoxes of material implication (view)

searching for Material implication 34 found (104 total)

alternate case: material implication

Material nonimplication (337 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article

used in generic circuits and Boolean algebra. It is the negation of material implication. That is to say that for any two propositions P {\displaystyle P}
If and only if (1,900 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
Q, P is equivalent (or materially equivalent) to Q (compare with material implication), P precisely if Q, P precisely (or exactly) when Q, P exactly in
List of philosophical problems (6,671 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
rather clear idea of what if-then means. In formal logic however, material implication defines if-then, which is not consistent with the common understanding
Implication graph (270 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
and each directed edge from vertex u to vertex v represents the material implication "If the literal u is true then the literal v is also true". Implication
Conditional quantifier (248 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
arbitrary formulas in one free variable): (The implication arrow denotes material implication in the metalanguage.) The minimal conditional logic M is characterized
Inclusion (Boolean algebra) (210 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article
arithmetic Boolean algebra, divisibility; in the algebra of propositions, material implication; in the two-element algebra, the set { (0,0), (0,1), (1,1) }. Some
Three-valued logic (3,292 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
AND C... = MIN(A, B, C ...) and A OR B OR C ... = MAX(A, B, C...). Material implication for Kleene logic can be defined as: A → B   = d e f   OR (   NOT
IMPLY gate (185 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
logic symbol right-facing arrow (→). Logically, it is equivalent to material implication, and the logical expression ¬A v B. There are two symbols for IMPLY
Categorical proposition (2,492 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
logic where a material implication statement P → Q {\displaystyle P\rightarrow Q} is converted (conversion) to another material implication statement Q
Contraposition (6,175 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
contrapositives are logically equivalent, we need to understand when material implication is true or false. P → Q {\displaystyle P\to Q} This is only false
List of logic symbols (256 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
\rightarrow ⊃ {\displaystyle \supset } \supset material conditional (material implication) implies, if P then Q, it is not the case that P and not Q propositional logic
Relevance (1,725 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
is implied by p breaks down because under standard definitions of material implication, a false proposition implies all other propositions. However though
Sum of Logic (736 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
'formal' consequences, which are roughly equivalent to the modern material implication and logical implication respectively. Similar accounts are given
Begriffsschrift (1,572 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
28, 31, 41, 52, 54, and 58 in the Begriffschrifft. (1)–(3) govern material implication, (4)–(6) negation, (7) and (8) identity, and (9) the universal quantifier
Peirce's law (1,425 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
logic where truth values are real numbers between 0 and 1, with material implication defined by: u → G v = { 1 , if  u ≤ v v , if  u > v {\displaystyle
Eby Friedman (2,206 words) [view diff] case mismatch in snippet view article find links to article
E. G. Friedman, A. Kolodny, and U. C. Weiser, "Memristor-Based Material Implication (IMPLY) Logic: Design Principles and Methodologies," IEEE Transactions
Outline of logic (2,119 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
NOR Logical biconditional Logical conjunction Logical disjunction Material implication Material nonimplication Negation Sheffer stroke Atomic formula Open
Errett Bishop (1,639 words) [view diff] no match in snippet view article find links to article
come to him after the lecture, to argue against his definition of (material) implication and in favour of the notion that the truth of the antecedent in
James F. Thomson (philosopher) (657 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article
(ed Pears, D.F.) New York: St. Martin's Press, 1963 In defense of material implication. Journal of Philosophy, 1966 Truth-bearers and the Trouble about
Identity of indiscernibles (2,356 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
biconditional operator ( ↔ {\displaystyle \leftrightarrow } ) in place of material implication ( → {\displaystyle \rightarrow } ).[citation needed] Indiscernibility
Rule of inference (7,293 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
{\displaystyle \to } in this formula means if ... then ..., expressing material implication. Logical operators or constants are expressions used to form and
Randolph diagram (890 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
Negation (not) ¬ , ~ Conjunction (and) & , ∧ Disjunction (or) ∨ Material implication (if...then) → {\displaystyle \rightarrow }  , ⇒ {\displaystyle \Rightarrow
Residuated Boolean algebra (1,155 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
multiplication • taken to be conjunction and both residuals taken to be material implication x→y. Of the remaining 15 binary Boolean operations that might be
Glossary of mathematical symbols (9,929 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
morphism from A to B. 3.  May denote a logical implication. For the material implication that is widely used in mathematics reasoning, it is nowadays generally
Counterfactual conditional (5,764 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
expresses necessity and → {\displaystyle \rightarrow } is understood as material implication. This approach was first proposed in 1912 by C.I. Lewis as part of
Boolean algebra (9,572 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
Material conditional The first operation, x → y, or Cxy, is called material implication. If x is true, then the result of expression x → y is taken to be
Gödel's ontological proof (4,409 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
first-order predicates) ⇒ {\displaystyle \Rightarrow } : "implies" (material implication) ∀ x {\displaystyle \forall x} : "For every x {\displaystyle x} "
Natural deduction (7,284 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
combination, which in turn is of lower precedence than the arrow, used for material implication; so no parentheses are needed to interpret this formula.) Syntactic
Józef Maria Bocheński (3,619 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
Mpq (F T F F)(p,q) Converse nonimplication Material conditional (Material implication) (T T F T)(p,q) Cpq Lpq (F F T F)(p,q) Material nonimplication Logical
History of logic (13,249 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
'formal' consequences, which are roughly equivalent to the modern material implication and logical implication respectively. Similar accounts are given
Memristor (13,731 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
Chattopadhyay, A.; Rakosi, Z. (2011). "Combinational logic synthesis for material implication". 2011 IEEE/IFIP 19th International Conference on VLSI and System-on-Chip
Bunched logic (2,856 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
rejected by relevantists in their bid to escape the `paradoxes of material implication', which are not a problem from the perspective of modelling resources
Propositional formula (11,131 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
→ of formal implication in the propositional calculus is called material implication to distinguish it from the everyday, intuitive implication. The use
Law of thought (11,576 words) [view diff] exact match in snippet view article find links to article
1912, 1997 edition page ix The "simple" type of implication, aka material implication, is the logical connective commonly symbolized by → or ⊃, e.g. p